Home  |  About us  |  Editorial board  |  Ahead of print  | Current issue  |  Archives  |  Submit article  |  Instructions |  Search  |   Subscribe  |  Advertise  |  Contacts  |  Login 
  Users Online: 270Home Print this page Email this page Small font sizeDefault font sizeIncrease font size  

 Table of Contents      
STATISTICS
Year : 2022  |  Volume : 13  |  Issue : 3  |  Page : 168-171

Research studies on screening tests


1 Jawaharlal Institute of Postgraduate Medical Education and Research, Puducherry, India
2 Department of Anaesthesiology, Tata Memorial Centre, Homi Bhabha National Institute, Mumbai, Maharashtra, India
3 Division of Thoracic Surgery, Tata Memorial Centre, Homi Bhabha National Institute, Mumbai, Maharashtra, India

Date of Submission15-May-2022
Date of Acceptance28-May-2022
Date of Web Publication30-Jun-2022

Correspondence Address:
Prof. Rakesh Aggarwal
Jawaharlal Institute of Postgraduate Medical Education and Research, Puducherry
India
Login to access the Email id

Source of Support: None, Conflict of Interest: None


DOI: 10.4103/picr.picr_111_22

Rights and Permissions
   Abstract 

Screening tests are done to diagnose asymptomatic disease in apparently healthy people with the aim to reduce mortality and morbidity from the disease. Certain criteria need to be fulfilled before we adopt population-level screening for any disease. Several biases exist in evaluating screening studies, and the ideal study design would be a randomized trial with hard endpoints such as mortality and morbidity.

Keywords: Diagnosis, mass screening, research methodology


How to cite this article:
Aggarwal R, Ranganathan P, Pramesh C S. Research studies on screening tests. Perspect Clin Res 2022;13:168-71

How to cite this URL:
Aggarwal R, Ranganathan P, Pramesh C S. Research studies on screening tests. Perspect Clin Res [serial online] 2022 [cited 2023 Mar 28];13:168-71. Available from: http://www.picronline.org/text.asp?2022/13/3/168/349320


   What is Screening? Top


A “screening test” refers to a medical test or procedure (often a laboratory or radiological test but can be a specific clinical examination or questionnaire) on a defined population of asymptomatic apparently healthy persons to sort them into those who probably have a disease and those who probably do not. The screening test is not always intended to be diagnostic, and those screened “positive” often need another confirmatory procedure or test.

Some common examples of screening are as follows: blood sugar measurement for early detection of diabetes/prediabetes, mammography for early detection of breast cancer, prostate-specific antigen measurement for prostate cancer, stool occult blood testing or colonoscopy for colon cancer, cholesterol level measurement to detect those at increased risk of cardiovascular disease, audiometric screening of newborn babies for hearing impairment, and antenatal ultrasound in pregnant women for the detection of fetal neural tube defect.

The rationale for screening is that if the disease or its precursor is identified early (before the manifestation of symptoms), then it may be possible to institute earlier treatment which in turn may lead to a cure or improved survival or better quality of life.


   Criteria for Screening Top


The introduction of a screening test in a population, though it may intuitively appear beneficial, often poses some challenges, such as the potential risk of a false-positive test result leading to unnecessary further testing, treatment and potential harm, and of additional cost, and is thus a subject of debate. Wilson and Jungner,[1],[2] in a landmark publication in 1968, stated 10 principles that have stood the test of time in guiding the discussion and decisions about the benefits, harm, costs, and ethics of screening programs (See [Box 1]).




   Qualities of a Test for Use as a Screening Test Top


An ideal test would perfectly separate those who have the condition from those who do not. However, in real life, no test is perfect, resulting in some healthy people having an abnormal or positive test result (false positive) and some people with the condition having a normal or negative screening result (false negative). We have discussed the performance characteristics of diagnostic tests, including sensitivity, specificity, positive predictive value, and negative predictive value in previous pieces in this series.[3],[4],[5]

It is important to note that since the prevalence of the disease among those screened is likely to be lower than in a clinic setting, the positive predictive values tend to be lower, and the number of false positives is higher in screening programs. It is therefore important to ensure that those who test positive on the screening test undergo further confirmatory testing.

The initial screening test should have a high sensitivity, besides being safe and cheap. By contrast, the confirmatory test should have a very high specificity. For instance, for colon cancer, fecal occult blood testing is used as a screening test, and those who test positive are then subjected to confirmation using colonoscopy and biopsy of any lesion that may be detected. Other examples include mammography, followed by tissue biopsy for breast cancer, serum prostate-specific antigen measurement, followed by image-guided prostatic biopsies.


   Assessment of Efficacy/Effectiveness of Screening Top


For a screening test to prove effective, it must not merely diagnose more cases of the disease of interest or diagnose cases earlier, but ultimately improve the outcome. For instance, screening for breast cancer using mammography must not merely diagnose more breast cancers or diagnose them at an early stage when treatment is possible, but it should reduce deaths due to breast cancer.

Ideally, the assessment of the value of a screening program requires a randomized controlled trial. An example would be the comparison of groups of women randomized to undergo mammography or clinical breast examination screening or otherwise, with the reduction in breast cancer-specific mortality as the expected endpoint.[6] However, such trials of screening programs need a large number of subjects and/or prolonged follow-up, making these quite challenging to do. Therefore, clinicians often resort to cohort studies (comparing outcomes of those who enroll for a screening program vs. those who do not) and, at times, case–control studies (i.e., comparison of cancers diagnosed as part of a screening program [cases of interest] and of cancers diagnosed as a part of routine clinical care [comparator or the controls]). However, these observational studies often exaggerate the benefits of the screening test due to a variety of biases.


   BIases in Observational Studies on Screening Programs Top


The biases inherent in the use of observational studies for assessing the effectiveness of screening programs are multifold; each of these is discussed in brief below. Of these lead time bias, length bias and detection (overdiagnosis) bias are forms of information bias and volunteer bias is a type of selection bias. These biases have been most well studied in relation to the use of screening tests for cancers.

Lead time bias

Lead time bias occurs because a screening test detects the disease at an earlier time point than when it would have been if it had been diagnosed by its clinical appearance. The difference between the two-time points (i.e., the time interval from diagnosis at screening to that of the likely detection after the occurrence of symptoms), during which the disease is asymptomatic, is referred to as “lead-time.” If in the persons whose disease is diagnosed during screening, survival time is measured from the time of such diagnosis, then the apparent increased survival time in the screened as compared with the control group may in truth be an artifactual difference [Figure 1].
Figure 1: Lead time bias. X-axis represents time in years. Two scenarios, namely where the disease is diagnosed in the usual clinical situation (after the occurrence of symptoms; top) and when the disease is diagnosed by screening (bottom), have been compared. Even though there is no real change in survival following early detection of disease by screening, the perceived duration of survival is increased, due to a lead time effect

Click here to view


Let us assume two women (A and B) who both have similar and small breast cancers that they are unaware of. Both are offered screening mammography in January 2022. Woman “A” decides to forego screening, the cancer remains undetected, finally being diagnosed in 2024 after becoming symptomatic and she lives till 2027. By comparison, the woman “B” undergoes mammography and is diagnosed immediately, receives treatment, and also dies in 2027. If the survival period is calculated in both cases from the respective time of diagnosis, it would seem to be longer for B (2022–2027, or 5 years) than for A (2024–2027, or 3 years). However, both the women lived the same amount of time and there has been no real gain in survival. Instead, screening appears to have resulted in falsely improved outcomes.

Length bias

This bias relates to the variability in the “length” of presymptomatic period for the disease (say breast cancer) that the screening test is intended to diagnose. All cancers are not identical, with some being aggressive and rapidly progressing, whereas others are indolent and slow-growing. Because the latter type has a longer presymptomatic period, they are likely to be overrepresented among the cancers picked up by screening.

This preferential picking up of the slower-growing tumors by the screening tests thus leads to an exaggeration of the apparent benefit [Figure 2]. This risk is even more likely when screening is done in older persons who are more likely to have slower-growing tumors and to die of competing causes.[7]
Figure 2: Length bias. X-axis represents time. Y-axis represents tumor size or stage. The disease onset is at zero and each oblique line represents tumor growth in an individual, with lines on the left for persons with rapid tumor growth and those on the right and bottom for those with slower tumor growth. The persons with rapid growth are diagnosed based on symptoms (D) and die (M) rapidly. By comparison, the individuals with slower growth are more likely to be diagnosed where they get screened (S), and they would live longer

Click here to view


Detection or overdiagnosis bias

This form of bias relates to an extreme form of “length bias,” whereby screening diagnoses a larger number of tumor cases that grow so slowly that these would not be expected to cause symptoms or death in a person's lifetime. Thus, even though screening leads to a large increase in the number of tumors diagnosed, it does not lead to an improvement in the overall outcome. This is best exemplified by screening for thyroid cancer, where the US Preventive Services Task Force found no substantial change in survival despite a massive increase in the number of diagnosed cases, leading it to issue a recommendation against such screening.[8]

Referral/volunteer bias (selection bias)

This form of bias relates to the possibility that persons who volunteer for screening differ from those who do not volunteer. It is likely that those who volunteer for screening are also more likely to be health conscious in other ways, and therefore more likely to have better overall health outcomes than those who do not. These differences, such as in their health status and behavioral factors, may influence the outcome of their diseases, leading to an apparent difference in survival rates in the screened and nonscreened cohorts.


   Other Considerations Top


As indicated above, a randomized controlled trial comparing groups of healthy persons offered screening and not offered screening is the best design to assess the benefits of a screening program. This design not only (almost) eliminates the risk of the several biases discussed above, but can also take into account compliance, i.e., the willingness to undergo a screening test in the first place. If a large part of the target population is unwilling to undergo a particular screening test, the latter would be expected to have very little impact. For example, in screening for colon cancer, the fecal occult blood test may, despite its lower sensitivity, be a more effective screening test because of a higher compliance rate, than colonoscopy which is a test with excellent sensitivity but low acceptability.

It has been argued that even in randomized controlled trials, it may be better to compare all-cause mortality, rather than disease-specific mortality. This is because the determination of the cause of death can be fickle/subjective. Let us consider a screening test for early cancer, which leads to treatment with an effective anticancer drug that is also cardiotoxic. If a proportion of those diagnosed early dies of drug toxicity, the group assigned to screening may appear to be benefited with fewer deaths attributed to cancer than the group not receiving screening though the total number of deaths may be unchanged, with the difference being accounted for by a greater number of cardiac deaths. However, the sample size required to demonstrate reduced overall mortality is likely to be unrealistically high, and very few screening trials have been done with that as the primary endpoint. A reasonable compromise would be to use disease-related mortality (which would also include treatment-related deaths) and use an independent blinded observer to attribute the cause of death.

Financial support and sponsorship

Nil.

Conflicts of interest

There are no conflicts of interest.

 
   References Top

1.
Wilson J, Junger G. Principles and Practice of Screening for Disease. Geneva: World Health Organization; 1968. Available from: https://apps.who.int/iris/bitstream/handle/10665/37650/WHO_PHP_34.pdf?sequence=17. [Last accessed on 2022 Apr 27].  Back to cited text no. 1
    
2.
Screening Programmes: A Short Guide. Increase Effectiveness, Maximize Benefits and Minimize Harm. Copenhagen: WHO Regional Office for Europe; 2020. Available from: https://apps.who.int/iris/bitstream/handle/10665/330829/9789289054782-eng.pdf. [Last accessed on 2022 Apr 27].  Back to cited text no. 2
    
3.
Ranganathan P, Aggarwal R. Common pitfalls in statistical analysis: Understanding the properties of diagnostic tests – Part 1. Perspect Clin Res 2018;9:40-3.  Back to cited text no. 3
[PUBMED]  [Full text]  
4.
Ranganathan P, Aggarwal R. Understanding the properties of diagnostic tests – Part 2: Likelihood ratios. Perspect Clin Res 2018;9:99-102.  Back to cited text no. 4
[PUBMED]  [Full text]  
5.
Aggarwal R, Ranganathan P. Understanding diagnostic tests – Part 3: Receiver operating characteristic curves. Perspect Clin Res 2018;9:145-8.  Back to cited text no. 5
[PUBMED]  [Full text]  
6.
Mittra I, Mishra GA, Dikshit RP, Gupta S, Kulkarni VY, Shaikh HKA, et al. Effect of screening by clinical breast examination on breast cancer incidence and mortality after 20 years: Prospective, cluster randomised controlled trial in Mumbai. BMJ 2021;372:n256.  Back to cited text no. 6
    
7.
Berry DA, Baines CJ, Baum M, Dickersin K, Fletcher SW, Gøtzsche PC, et al. Flawed inferences about screening mammography's benefit based on observational data. J Clin Oncol 2009;27:639-40.  Back to cited text no. 7
    
8.
US Preventive Services Task Force; Bibbins-Domingo K, Grossman DC, Curry SJ, Barry MJ, Davidson KW, et al. Screening for thyroid cancer: US preventive services task force recommendation statement. JAMA 2017;317:1882-7.  Back to cited text no. 8
    


    Figures

  [Figure 1], [Figure 2]



 

Top
  
 
  Search
 
    Similar in PUBMED
   Search Pubmed for
   Search in Google Scholar for
 Related articles
    Access Statistics
    Email Alert *
    Add to My List *
* Registration required (free)  

 
  In this article
    Abstract
   What is Screening?
    Criteria for Scr...
    Qualities of a T...
    Assessment of Ef...
    BIases in Observ...
   Other Considerations
    References
    Article Figures

 Article Access Statistics
    Viewed963    
    Printed52    
    Emailed0    
    PDF Downloaded172    
    Comments [Add]    

Recommend this journal